Skip to main content
Log in

Against the secret ballot: Toward a new proposal for open voting

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Acta Politica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The secret ballot is considered a central feature of free and fair elections all over the world. While the reasons to uphold it seem to be overwhelming, we argue that the secret ballot is only second-best at best and that a modified version of open voting might prove to be more democratic. Instead of denying the various problems and difficulties that an open system might encounter, we want to offer a genuine proposal that can avoid these numerous pitfalls. After rehearsing the various arguments pro and contra open voting, we draw attention to the role of shame, which has been neglected by both sides in the debate. While shame plays a pivotal role in the democratic argument pro open voting, it also brings out new problems that tell against opening up the vote. This means that, if we want to draw on the democratic potential of open voting, we will have to find a system that minimizes the undesirable effects of shame. In the third and final section, we will formulate a concrete proposal of open voting that we believe is more democratic than the current secret ballot and is able to avoid potential worries. Even if this proves to be highly speculative, it serves as an invitation for further empirical research.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Figure 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. As Przeworski (1998, p. 140) rightly points out, deliberation can only be called democratic if a ‘discussion intended to change the preferences on the bases of which people decide how to act (…) leads to a decision binding on a community’. If deliberation has no consequences for the public, then it is mere cheap talk or window-dressing.

  2. This is aptly explained in a quote attributed to Benjamin Franklin: ‘democracy is two wolves and a lamb voting on what to have for lunch’.

  3. While reinvigorating the public sphere was deliberative democracy’s initial concern, it is nowadays primarily studied and implemented on a much smaller scale, that is, in so-called mini-publics (Niemeyer, 2011, p. 103). We think that doing away with the complete secrecy of the ballot – which was partly responsible for the corruption of the public sphere – fits with deliberative democracy’s initial program and tallies perfectly well with other recent attempts to stimulate deliberation on a larger scale (such as Niemeyer’s own focus on how to communicate the outcomes of mini-publics to the broader public).

  4. ‘In such a case as that of the repudiating states of North America, is there not some check to the unprincipled voter in the shame of looking an honest man in the face?’ (Mill (1862[1991], p. 219)

  5. In Sweden, voters can get their ballot papers (with the party name printed on it) from party workers at the polling station. This is close to Brennan and Pettit’s proposal. The most important difference, however, is that Swedish voters retain the opportunity to keep their votes secret by picking up blank ballot papers (Valmyndigheten, s.d., p. 9). As we discuss in what follows, we believe – contra the Swedish system – that nobody should escape (potential) ‘exposure’, and yet – contra Brennan and Pettit – that voters should not be exposed to their peers but to fellow citizens.

  6. Here, we do not discuss how these groups should be selected and organized, how all this should be funded or what the ‘penalty’ should be for not participating. With respect to the first question, we think that recent work by deliberative democrats on various forms of mini-publics can be highly useful (Goodin and Dryzek, 2006). In short, it is essential for such groups to have a trained and neutral moderator that guarantees the deliberative nature of the discussions. In addition, people’s votes should be revealed only within the seclusion of these groups.

  7. The so-called ‘social desirability bias’ refers to the widely documented tendency of respondents to behave in ways that they think will be viewed favorably by the people observing them. If people think the expression of their opinion is public, they can feel under pressure to provide an answer that is deemed more publicly acceptable. As the so-called ‘Bradley-effect’ shows, this mechanism can have an impact in politics with fewer people expressing racist preferences in polls than in elections.

References

  • Ackerman, B.A. and Fishkin, J.S. (2004) Deliberation Day. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barbalet, J. (2002) Secret voting and political emotions. Mobilization: An International Quarterly 7 (2): 129–140.

    Google Scholar 

  • Birch, S. and Watt, B. (2004) Remote electronic voting: Free, fair and secret? The Political Quarterly 75 (1): 60–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G. and Pettit, P. (1990) Unveiling the vote. British Journal of Political Science 20 (3): 311–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J. (1998) Democracy and liberty. In: J. Elster (ed.) Deliberative Democracy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, pp. 185–231.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Crook, M. and Crook, T. (2007) The advent of the secret ballot in Britain and France, 1789–1914: From public assembly to private compartment. History 92 (308): 449–471.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elklit, J. (1983) Mobilization and partisan division: Open voting in Fredericia, Denmark. Social Science History 7 (3): 235–266.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. (1997) The market and the forum: Three varieties of political theory. In: J. Bohman and W. Rehg (eds.) Deliberative Democracy: Essays on Reason and Politics. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, pp. 3–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gambetta, D. (1998) ‘Claro!’: An essay on discursive machismo. In: J. Elster (ed.) Deliberative Democracy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, pp. 19–43.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Goodin, R.E. and Dryzek, J.S. (2006) Deliberative impacts: The macro-political uptake of mini-publics. Politics & Society 34 (2): 219–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gosseries, A. (2005) Publicity. In: E.N. Zalta (ed.) Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford, CA: The Metaphysics Research Lab.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gutmann, A. and Thompson, D. (2004) Why Deliberative Democracy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1975) Legitimation Crisis. Translated by T. McCarthy. Boston, MA: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hill, G.E. (1891) The secret ballot. The Yale Law Journal 1 (1): 26–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hooge, I.E., Breugelmans, S.M. and Zeelenberg, M. (2008) Not so ugly after all: When shame acts as a commitment device. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 95 (4): 933–943.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kinzer, B.L. (1978) The un-englishness of the secret ballot. Albion Quarterly Journal Concerned with British Studies 10 (3): 237–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lever, A. (2007) Mill and the secret ballot: Beyond coercion and corruption. Utilitas 19 (3): 354–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manion, J. (2002) The moral relevance of shame. American Philosophical Quarterly 39 (1): 73–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J.S. (1862 [1991]) Considerations on Representative Government. New York: Prometheus Books.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, J.C. (2008) Organization of Opinion: Open Voting in England, 1832–68. Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Niemeyer, S. (2011) The emancipatory effect of deliberation: Empirical lessons from mini-publics. Politics & Society 39 (1): 103–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M.C. (2004) Hiding from Humanity: Disgust, Shame, and the Law. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Przeworski, A. (1998) Deliberation and ideological domination. In: J. Elster (ed.) Deliberative Democracy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, pp. 140–160.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J.-P. (1973) Élections, piège à cons. Les temps modernes 318 (1): 100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. (1776) An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations. London: W. Strahan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Van Hagen, E. (2005) The not-so-secret ballot: How Washington fails to provide a secret vote for impaired voters as required by the Washington State Constitution. Washington Law Review 80: 787–817.

    Google Scholar 

  • Valmyndigheten (Swedish Election Authority). (s.d.) Elections in Sweden, http://www.val.se/pdf/electionsinsweden_webb.pdf, accessed 26 February 2013.

  • Velleman, D. (2001) The genesis of shame. Philosophy and Public Affairs 30 (1): 27–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Engelen, B., Nys, T. Against the secret ballot: Toward a new proposal for open voting. Acta Polit 48, 490–507 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1057/ap.2013.10

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1057/ap.2013.10

Keywords

Navigation