Skip to main content
Log in

Critical republicanism: Jürgen Habermas and Chantal Mouffe

  • Article
  • Published:
Contemporary Political Theory Aims and scope

Abstract

Jürgen Habermas’s theory of ‘discourse ethics’ has been an important source of inspiration for theories of deliberative democracy and is typically contrasted with agonistic conceptions of democracy represented by theorists such as Chantal Mouffe. In this article I show that this contrast is overstated. By focusing on the different philosophical traditions that underpin Mouffe’s and Habermas’s respective approaches, commentators have generally overlooked the political similarities between these thinkers. I examine Habermas’s and Mouffe’s respective conceptions of democratic politics and argue that they cannot be so neatly distinguished from each other. I show that much of Mouffe’s criticism of Habermas’s theory does not hold up to careful scrutiny, and discourse ethics shares important points of similarity with her own democratic theory. By using critical republican theory to show the similarities in their work, I push beyond the agonistic versus deliberative debate, and show that at the heart of both of these approaches is a critical republican emphasis on the need for civic solidarity, on the constructive role of conflict in democratic politics and on the vital importance of self-government. These are crucial ingredients for the regeneration of democracy in contemporary pluralistic societies.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Dryzek 2000 and Brady 2004.

  2. See Boucher 2005 for a republican interpretation of Oakeshott’s work.

  3. Seyla Benhabib (1990) and Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson (1996) read the term moral in discourse ethics to refer to individual moral judgments. Benhabib (1990, pp. 346–347) says that the term moral ‘if interpreted correctly could help our [individual] moral intuitions’. Moreover, in discussions about the tensions between agonistic and deliberative approaches, Kapoor (2002), Brady 2004 and Schaap (2006) all reiterate Mouffe’s view that Habermas defends an essentially Kantian inspired conception of morality.

  4. Both Knops 2007 and Olson 2009 have identified similarities between the deliberative and agonistic theories of democracy.

  5. Mouffe rejects cosmopolitanism, and she emphasises the renewal of democracy at the local level, at the level the nation state and at the regional level, such as the Europe Union (Mouffe, 2005, pp. 107, 128).

  6. Habermas’s (1994) privileging of communicative action over rhetoric is unsustainable and inconsistent. Contrary to (Habermas 1984, pp. 285–286), rhetoric is not a calculated activity in the manner of rational choice theory, but a key strategy of deliberation and central to a thriving and participatory polity. Indeed, deliberative democrats such as John Dryzek acknowledge the power of rhetoric. He cites Martin Luther King, Jr’s speeches as a paradigmatic example of the potentially progressive power of non-rational forms of communication (Dryzek, 2000, pp. 51–52, 101).

  7. Both (Habermas 1992, p. 141) and Mouffe emphasise the need for the construction of a common will to work against the danger of a de-centered or ‘fragmented’ society. The way in which the common will is forged differs in each account. For Habermas, it needs to be based on the solidarity of an unforced agreement but is not necessarily free from conflict, whereas for Mouffe it entails both force and consent.

  8. (Habermas 1998, p. 227) says that the ‘ethical substance of a political integration that unites the citizens of the nation must remain “neutral” with respect to the differences between the ethical-cultural communities within the nation, each of which is integrated around it own conception of the good’. The diverse ethical communities are integrated around a conception of morality that is able to command a degree of loyalty but cannot be legally enforced.

References

  • Baynes, K. (1995) Democracy and the Rechtsstaat: Remarks on Habermas’s Faktizität und Geltung. In: S.K. White (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Habermas. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benhabib, S. (1990) Afterword: Communicative ethics and contemporary controversies in practical philosophy. In: S. Benhabib and F.R. Dallmayr (eds) The Communicative Ethics Controversy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 330–70.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berlin, I. (ed.) (1969 [1958]) Two concepts of liberty. In: Four Essays on Liberty. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 118–172.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickford, S. (1996) The Dissonance of Democracy: Listening, Conflict and Citizenship. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohman, J. (1994) Complexity, pluralism, and the constitutional state: On Habermas’s Faktizitat and Geltung. Law and Society Review 28 (4): 897–930.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boucher, D. (2005) Oakeshott, freedom and republicanism. British Journal of Politics and International Relations 7 (1): 81–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brady, J.S. (2004) No contest? Assessing the agonistic critiques of Jürgen Habermas’s Theory of the public sphere. Philosophy and Social Criticism 30 (3): 331–354.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Connolly, W.E. (1995) The Ethos of Pluralization. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dryzek, J. (2000) Deliberative Democracy and Beyond: Liberals, Critics, Contestations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gutmann, A. and Thompson, D. (1996) Democracy and Disagreement. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1977) Hannah Arendt’s communications concept of power. Social Research 44 (1): 2–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1984) The Theory of Communicative Action. Vol. 1. Cambridge, UK: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1987) The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity. Cambridge, UK: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1988) Legitimation Crisis. Cambridge, UK: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1989) The New Conservative. Cambridge, UK: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1990) Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action. Cambridge, UK: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1992) Post-Metaphysical Thinking. Cambridge, UK: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1993) Justification and Application. Cambridge: Polity Press, UK.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1996) Between Facts and Norms Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy. Cambridge, UK: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1998) Inclusion of the Other: Studies in Political Theory. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (2001a) Constitutional democracy? A paradoxical union of contradictory principles. Political Theory 29 (6): 766–781.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (2001b) The Postnational Constellation: Political Essays. Cambridge, UK: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (2004) Tolerance – The pacemaker for cultural rights. Philosophy 79 (1): 5–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, G.W.F. (1991) Elements of the Philosophy of Right. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honig, B. (2007) Between decision and deliberation: Political paradox in democratic theory. American Political Science Review 101 (1): 1–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kapoor, I. (2002) Deliberative democracy or agonistic pluralism? The relevance of the Habermas - Mouffe Debate for Third World Politics. Alternatives: Global, Local, Global, Political 27 (4): 459–487.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Khan, G (2012a) Habermas and Oakeshott on rationalism, morality and democratic politics. Political Studies 60 (2): 381–398.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Khan, G. (2012b) Politics and morality in Habermas’ discourse ethics. Philosophy Social Criticism 38 (2): 149–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knops, A. (2007) Debate: Agonism as deliberation – On Mouffe’s Theory of democracy. Journal of Political Philosophy 15 (1): 115–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laborde, C. (2008) Critical Republicanism: The Hijab Controversy and Political Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Laborde, C. and Mayor, J. (eds.) (2008) Republicanism and Political Theory. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Larmore, C. (1999) The moral basis of political liberalism. The Journal of Philosophy 96 (12): 599–625.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lyotard, J.-F. (1984) The Post-Modern Condition: A Report on Knowledge. Manchester: Manchester University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Markell, P. (1997) Contesting consensus: Rereading Habermas on the public sphere. Constellations 3 (3): 377–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCarthy, J. (1990) Introduction. In: Habermas, J. (ed.), Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action. Cambridge, UK: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mouffe, C. (ed.) (1992) Democratic citizenship and the political community. In: Dimension of Radical Democracy: Pluralism, Citizenship, Community. London: Verso, pp. 225–239.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mouffe, C. (1993) The Return of the Political. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mouffe, C. (ed.) (1999) Carl Schmitt and the paradox of liberal democracy. In: The Challenge of Carl Schmitt. London: Verso, pp. 38–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mouffe, C. (2000) The Democratic Paradox. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mouffe, C. (2005) On the Political. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oakeshott, M. (1975) On Human Conduct. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson, J. (2009) Friends and enemies, slaves and masters: Fanaticism, Wendell Phillips and the limits of democratic theory. Journal of Politics 71 (1): 82–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. (1997) Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rehg, W. (1994) Insight and Solidarity. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaap, A. (2006) Agonism in divided societies. Philosophy and Social Criticism 32 (2): 255–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, M.N.S. (1998) The Scared Fire of Liberty. New York: New York University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, Q. (1998) Liberty before Liberalism. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, Q. (2002) Visions of Politics: Volume II: Renaissance Virtues. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Joel Olson and Mark Wenman for their constructive comments on this article. I would also like to thank the two anonymous referees for their helpful suggestions. This article is dedicated to the late Joel Olson who did not just interpret the world but actively tried to change it for the better. May your ethos, struggle against inequality, and passion for life, emancipation and freedom provide an example to us all.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Khan, G. Critical republicanism: Jürgen Habermas and Chantal Mouffe. Contemp Polit Theory 12, 318–337 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1057/cpt.2013.3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1057/cpt.2013.3

Keywords

Navigation