Skip to main content
Log in

Political imagination and the crime of crimes: Coming to terms with ‘genocide’ and ‘genocide blindness’

  • Article
  • Published:
Contemporary Political Theory Aims and scope

Abstract

This article deals critically with the process of coming to terms with ‘genocide’. It starts from the observation that conventional philosophical and legal approaches to capturing the essence of ‘genocide’ through an improved definition necessarily fail to adapt to the ever-changing nature of political violence. Faced with this challenge, the article suggests that the contemporary debate on genocide (and its denial) should be complemented with a focus on transforming the perceptive and interpretive frameworks through which acts of violence are discussed in the public sphere. The main purpose of this article is to contribute, from the vantage point of political theory, to this debate by offering a novel normative perspective on negative reactions to genocide. Hence I argue that it is productive to speak of ‘genocide blindness’ in cases when the members of the public sphere are simply incapable of seeing an instance of violence as genocidal. To establish this claim, the article introduces Ludwig Wittgenstein’s reflections on ‘aspect-seeing’ so as to underline the importance of changing the way that political violence is perceived and interpreted. In a second step, the article turns to María Pía Lara’s theory of storytelling as a concrete mechanism for triggering and instituting this kind of change.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For a deflationary position regarding the practical effect of the word ‘genocide’ see Glanville, 2009.

  2. Throughout this article I intend to use ‘term’ and ‘word’ synonymously, and keep them apart from ‘concept’. This terminology reflects the concerns expressed by Wittgenstein about many uses of ‘concept’, which are summarized above.

  3. From academic circles, the debate regularly spills over into the judicial arena. Sometimes genocide deniers take recourse to challenging the soundness of historical scholarship in the courtroom, as it has recently been the case in Irving v. Lipstadt, with its devastating ruling on David Irving’s ruminations (Evans, 2001).

  4. I thank an anonymous reviewer for urging me to clarify this point.

  5. For a very strong (and disputed) equation of ‘Holocaust denial’ and ‘climate change denial’ see Tomkiewicz (2011). For a more refined appraisal of environmental factors of violence see Homer-Dixon (1999). For the case of Tuvalu see Barnett (2003). For another position arguing that genocide can only be fought effectively if its social, economic and environmental pre-conditions – massive global inequality and predatory capitalism – are eradicated, see Levene (2004).

  6. The idea that Wittgenstein may teach political theorists something crucial is not new. Following in the footsteps of Hanna Pitkin, several authors have attempted to recover Wittgenstein’s potential for exploring diverse political phenomena. See Holt (1997); Mouffe (2000); Pitkin (1972); Pleasants (1999); Tully (1989); Zerilli (1998). A recent book (Robinson, 2009) even seeks to systematize political theory’s reception of Wittgenstein in general.

  7. The following passages owe their existence to the perceptive and constructive criticism of one of the reviewers. I am very grateful for having been directed towards a better understanding of Wittgenstein in the context of ‘essentially contested concepts’.

  8. Many of these authors take their cues from Stanley Cavell’s influential interpretation (Cavell, 1999). Cavell refers at several points to Wittgenstein’s discussion of ‘aspect-seeing’ (Cavell, 1981, p. 36; 2007, pp. 282–283) For a very interesting use of ‘aspect-seeing’ in the analysis of ‘liberty’, see Havercroft (2003). For a feminist appropriation of Wittgenstein’s reflections, see Heyes (2007, pp. 15–37).

  9. In what follows, I will use ‘genealogy’ and ‘narratives’ as largely synonymous. This is obviously not fully compatible with Owen’s account of liberation from aspectival captivity. However, for my purpose it is important to emphasize the different fora in which ‘emancipation and enlightenment’ can occur. Storytelling in precisely Lara’s sense appears to be the most promising manner to instil citizens with ‘a new way of seeing things’.

  10. On the relation between individual and collective dimensions of storytelling, see Appiah (2005, pp. 22–23).

  11. Some scholars prefer to use the Hebrew word ‘Shoah’ instead of ‘Holocaust’. For a comprehensive account of both terms, see Petrie (2000).

  12. For a recent contribution to the Holocaust debate that triggered a semantic shock, consider for example Timothy Snyder’s concept of ‘bloodlands’ (Snyder, 2010).

  13. See: Husanovic (2009); Koebel (2009); Todorova (2011).

  14. In fact, both reviewers as well as the journal’s editors have pressed me to clarify my position vis-à-vis the narrative approach’s normative foundations. I thank them for their perceptive remarks.

  15. On the futility of (some types of) ethical theory for moral reasoning, see Williams (1981, pp. ix–x).

  16. To be sure, powerful stories will often come perilously close to proselytizing, especially when their objective is to move the imagination of the public – the media frenzy around the Kony 2012 campaign, for example, testifies to the thin line separating manipulative from non-manipulative storytelling (Waldorf, 2012; Cadwalladr, 2013).

  17. This notion of a critical community of spectators could be further elaborated with reference to Jeffrey Green’s (2010) model of plebiscitary democracy.

References

  • Abed, M. (2006) Clarifying the concept of genocide. Metaphilosophy 37 (3-4): 308–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anon. (2012a) Srebrenica deaths ‘not genocide’ [online], 1 June, BBC. http://www.bbc.co.uk/news/world-europe-18301196.

  • Anon. (2012b) Syria’s Srebrenica [online], Wall Street Journal 28 May. http://online.wsj.com/article/SB10001424052702303807404577432561861499408.html.

  • Appiah, A. (2005) The Ethics of Identity. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. (1998) The Human Condition, 2nd edn. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Barnett, J. (2003) Security and climate change. Global Environmental Change 13 (1): 7–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baz, A. (2000) What’s the point of seeing aspects? Philosophical Investigations 23 (2): 97–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beachler, D.W. (2011) The Genocide Debate: Politicians, Academics, and Victims. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bellamy, A.J. (2005) Responsibility to protect or Trojan horse? The crisis in Darfur and humanitarian intervention after Iraq. Ethics & International Affairs 19 (2): 31–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bellamy, A.J. (2012) Getting away with mass murder. Journal of Genocide Research 14 (1): 29–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benhabib, S. (1990) Hannah Arendt and the redemptive power of narrative. Social Research 57 (1): 167–196.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloxham, D. (2009) The Final Solution: A Genocide. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Boghossian, P. (2010) The concept of genocide. Journal of Genocide Research 12 (1): 69–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cadwalladr, C. (2013) Jason Russell: Kony 2012 and the fight for truth [online], The Observer 3 March. http://www.guardian.co.uk/world/2013/mar/03/jason-russell-kony-2012-interview.

  • Cavell, S. (1981) Pursuits of Happiness: The Hollywood Comedy of Remarriage. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavell, S. (1999) The Claim of Reason: Wittgenstein, Skepticism, Morality, and Tragedy, new edn. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavell, S. (2007) Companionable thinking. In: A. Crary (ed.) Wittgenstein and the Moral Life: Essays in Honor of Cora Diamond. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 281–298.

    Google Scholar 

  • Charny, I.W. (2003) A classification of denials of the Holocaust and other genocides. Journal of Genocide Research 5 (1): 11–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, J. (2007) Raphael Lemkin and the Struggle for the Genocide Convention. Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Day, W. and Krebs, V.J. (eds.) (2010) Seeing Wittgenstein Anew. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Disch, L. (1993) More truth than fact: Storytelling as critical understanding in the writings of Hannah Arendt. Political Theory 21 (4): 665–694.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eboe-Osuji, C. (2007) Rape as genocide: Some questions arising. Journal of Genocide Research 9 (2): 251–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, R.J. (2001) Lying about Hitler: History, Holocaust, and the David Irving Trial. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, M. (ed.) (2007) Peacebuilding and Civil Society in Bosnia-Herzegovina: Ten Years After Dayton. 2nd edn. Berlin and Münster, Germany: Lit Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeden, M. (1998) Ideologies and Political Theory: A Conceptual Approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Freeden, M. (2004) Editorial: Essential contestability and effective contestability. Journal of Political Ideologies 9 (1): 3–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freeden, M. (2005) What should the ‘political’ in political theory explore? Journal of Political Philosophy 13 (2): 113–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, A. (2009) Words matter: Genocide and the definitional debate [online]. Centre for the Study of Genocide and Mass Violence at the University of Sheffield (UK), http://www.genocidecentre.dept.shef.ac.uk/documents/Paper%20-%20Adrian%20Gallagher.pdf.

  • Gallie, W.B. (1955–1956) Essentially contested concepts. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 56: 167–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glanville, L. (2009) Is ‘genocide’ still a powerful word? Journal of Genocide Research 11 (4): 467–486.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glock, H.-J. (ed.) (1996) Aspect-perception. In: A Wittgenstein Dictionary. Oxford and Cambridge: Blackwell Reference, pp. 36–40.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gourevitch, P. (1998) We Wish to Inform You that Tomorrow we will be Killed with Our Families: Stories from Rwanda. New York: Farrar, Straus & Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Green, J.E. (2010) The Eyes of the People: Democracy in an Age of Spectatorship. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gunnell, J.G. (2011) Political Theory and Social Science: Cutting against the Grain. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gunnell, J.G. (2013) Leaving everything as it is: Political inquiry after Wittgenstein. Contemporary Political Theory 12 (2): 80–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1998) Learning by disaster? A diagnostic look back on the short 20th century. Constellations 5 (3): 307–320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hagan, J. and Rymond-Richmond, W. (eds.) (2009) Darfur and the Crime of Genocide. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Havercroft, J. (2003) On seeing liberty as. In: C. J. Heyes (ed.) The Grammar of Politics: Wittgenstein and Political Philosophy. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, pp. 149–164.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herf, J. (2006) The Jewish Enemy: Nazi Propaganda during World War II and the Holocaust. Cambridge: Belknap Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Herzog, D. (1985) Without Foundations: Justification in Political Theory. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hester, M.B. (1966) Metaphor and aspect seeing. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 25 (2): 205–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heyes, C.J. (2007) Self-transformations: Foucault, Ethics, and Normalized Bodies. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Holt, R. (1997) Wittgenstein, Politics and Human Rights. London and New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Homer-Dixon, T.F. (1999) Environment, Scarcity, and Violence. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husanovic, J. (2009) The politics of gender, witnessing, postcoloniality and trauma: Bosnian feminist trajectories. Feminist Theory 10 (1): 99–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koebel, C. (2009) Torture, maternity, and truth in Jasmila Zbanic’s Grbavica: Land of My Dreams [online], Jump Cut: A Review of Contemporary Media (51). http://www.ejumpcut.org/archive/jc51.2009/Grvbavica/index.html.

  • Korski, D. (2012) A Syrian Srebrenica? [online], The Spectator 4 February. http://www.thespectator.co.uk/coffeehouse/politics/2012/january/week-beginning-30-january--2012/a-syrian-srebrenica.

  • Lara, M. (2007) Narrating Evil: A Postmetaphysical Theory of Reflective Judgment. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lee, S. (2009) The moral distinctiveness of genocide. Journal of Political Philosophy 18 (3): 335–356.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lemkin, R. (2008) Axis Rule in Occupied Europe: Laws of Occupation, Analysis of Government, Proposals for Redress, 2nd edn. Clark, NJ: Lawbook Exchange.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levene, M. (2004) A dissenting voice: Part II. Journal of Genocide Research 6 (3): 431–445.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lister, T. (2012) Syria, Sarajevo and Srebrenica: When outrage isn’t enough [online], 29 May, CNN. http://articles.cnn.com/2012-05-29/middleeast/world_meast_syria-sarajevo-and-srebrenica_1_srebrenica-bosnian-serb-forces-sarajevo?_s=PM:MIDDLEEAST, accessed 19 June 2012.

  • Luban, D. (1983) Explaining dark times: Hannah Arendt’s theory of theory. Social Research 50 (1): 215–248.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luban, D. (2006) Calling genocide by its rightful name: Lemkin’s word, Darfur, and the UN report. Chicago Journal of International Law 7 (1): 303–320.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A.C. (1984) After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory, 2nd edn. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macleod, C. (2012) An alternative approach to the harm of genocide. Politics 32 (3): 197–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mamdani, M. (2009) Saviours and Survivors: Darfur, Politics, and the War on Terror. Cape Town, South Africa: HSRC Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mamdani, M. (2010) Responsibility to protect or right to punish? Journal of Intervention and Statebuilding 4 (1): 53–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • May, L. (2010) Genocide: A Normative Account. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, S.C. (2009) Moral injury and relational harm: Analyzing rape in Darfur. Journal of Social Philosophy 40 (4): 504–523.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moses, A.D. (2002) Conceptual blockages and definitional dilemmas in the ‘racial century’: Genocides of indigenous peoples and the Holocaust. Patterns of Prejudice 36 (4): 7–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moshman, D. (2001) Conceptual constraints on thinking about genocide. Journal of Genocide Research 3 (3): 431–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mouffe, C. (2000) Wittgenstein, political theory and democracy. The Democratic Paradox. London: Verso, pp. 60–79.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norval, A.J. (2006) Democratic identification. Political Theory 34 (2): 229–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Owen, D. (2002) Criticism and captivity: On genealogy and critical theory. European Journal of Philosophy 10 (2): 216–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petrie, J. (2000) The secular word Holocaust: Scholarly myths, history, and 20th century meanings. Journal of Genocide Research 2 (1): 31–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pitkin, H.F. (1972) Wittgenstein and Justice: On the Significance of Ludwig Wittgenstein for Social and Political Thought. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pleasants, N. (1999) Wittgenstein and the Idea of a Critical Social Theory: A Critique of Giddens, Habermas, and Bhaskar. London and New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Posner, E.A. (2009) The Perils of Global Legalism. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Powell, C. (2007) What do genocides kill? A relational conception of genocide. Journal of Genocide Research 9 (4): 527–547.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Power, S. (2002) A Problem from Hell: America and the Age of Genocide. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Preston, P. (2011) Remember Srebrenica? The West’s intervention in Libya is a no-brainer [online], Guardian 29 May. http://www.guardian.co.uk/commentisfree/2011/may/29/srebrenica-libya-intervention-no-brainer.

  • Rangelov, I. and Theros, M. (2010) Transitional justice in Bosnia and Herzegovina: Coherence and complementarity of EU institutions and civil society. In: K. Ambos, J. Large and M. Wierda (eds.) Building a Future on Peace and Justice: Studies on Transnational Justice, Peace and Development. Berlin, Germany: Springer, pp. 357–389.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ripstein, A. (1987) Foundationalism in political theory. Philosophy and Public Affairs 16 (2): 115–137.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, C.C. (2009) Wittgenstein and Political Theory: The View from Somewhere. Edinburgh, UK: Edinburgh University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schabas, W. (2001) Hate speech in Rwanda: The road to genocide. McGill Law Journal 46 (1): 141–171.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schabas, W. (2009) Genocide in International Law: The Crime of Crimes, 2nd edn. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Scheffer, D. (2006) Genocide and atrocity crimes. Genocide Studies and Prevention 1 (3): 229–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schott, R.M. (2011) War rape, natality and genocide. Journal of Genocide Research 13 (1-2): 5–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shklar, J.N. (1986) Legalism: Law, Morals, and Political Trials. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simms, B. (2011) Road to Libya runs through Srebrenica [online], Independent 29 May. http://www.independent.co.uk/opinion/commentators/brendan-simms-road-to-libya-runs-through-srebrenica-2290326.html.

  • Snyder, T. (2010) Bloodlands: Europe between Hitler and Stalin. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Speight, A. (2011) Arendt on narrative theory and practice. College Literature 38 (1): 115–130.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stone, D. (2004) The historiography of genocide: Beyond ‘uniqueness’ and ethnic competition. Rethinking History 8 (1): 127–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Straus, S. (2001) Contested meanings and conflicting imperatives: A conceptual analysis of genocide. Journal of Genocide Research 3 (3): 349–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. (1989) Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Theriault, H.C. (2010) Genocidal mutation and the challenge of definition. Metaphilosophy 41 (4): 481–524.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Todorova, T. (2011) ‘Giving memory a future’: Confronting the legacy of mass rape in post-conflict Bosnia-Herzegovina. Journal of International Women’s Studies 12 (2): 3–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomkiewicz, M. (2011) Climate Change: The Fork at the End of Now. New York: Momentum Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Totten, S. and Bartrop, R. (2008) Genocide, denial of. In: Dictionary of Genocide. Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, pp. 163–164.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tully, J. (1989) Wittgenstein and political philosophy: Understanding practices of critical reflection. Political Theory 17 (2): 172–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Udombana, N.J. (2005) When neutrality is a sin: The Darfur crisis and the crisis of humanitarian intervention in Sudan. Human Rights Quarterly 27 (4): 1149–1199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Verdeja, E. (2009) Narrating evil: A post-metaphysical theory of reflective judgment by María Pía Lara. Constellations 16 (2): 355–357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Waal, A. (2007) Darfur and the failure of the responsibility to protect. International Affairs 83 (6): 1039–1054.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waldorf, L. (2012) White noise: Hearing the disaster. Journal of Human Rights Practice 4 (3): 469–474.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1981) Moral Luck: Philosophical Papers, 1973–1980. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, D. and Bellamy, A.J. (2005) The responsibility to protect and the crisis in Darfur. Security Dialogue 36 (1): 27–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (2009) Philosophical Investigations, revised 4th edn. In: P.M.S. Hacker and J. Schulte. (eds.) Translated by G.E.M. Anscombe, M.S. Hacker and J. Schulte. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.

  • Zbanic, J. (dir.) (2006) Grbavica: The Land of My Dreams. Dogwoof Pictures.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zerilli, L.M.G. (1998) Doing without knowing: Feminism’s politics of the ordinary. Political Theory 26 (4): 435–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zolo, D. (2002) Invoking Humanity: War, Law and Global Order. London and New York: Continuum Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Earlier versions of this article were presented on three different occasions: at the Ideals and Reality in Social Ethics conference in Caerleon (2012); during the Meetings on Ethics and Political Philosophy in Braga (2012); and in the Political Theory Research Group seminar in Edinburgh (2012). I greatly benefitted from the vibrant discussions at all these events. Moreover, I owe thanks to several (old and new) colleagues, whose generous and sharp feedback helped me in refining the ideas defended in this article: André Barrinha, Matteo Bonotti, Liz Cripps, Christina Dineen, Alessandro Ferrara, Tim Hayward, Alex Latham, Chris Macleod, João Cardoso Rosas, Ashley Taylor and Alan Wilson. David Owen set the article on a more promising track when he kindly pointed me to his own work on Wittgenstein. As always, Mihaela Mihai most carefully read and charitably commented on the manuscript at various stages. Last but not least, I express my sincere gratitude to the editors as well as to the two anonymous referees of this journal for their constructive criticisms, and encouragements. Special thanks go to Sam Chambers for expertly guiding the manuscript through the review process. The usual disclaimers apply.

Financial support: The research for this article has been supported by a Marie Curie Career Integration Grant within the 7th Framework Programme of the European Community.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Thaler, M. Political imagination and the crime of crimes: Coming to terms with ‘genocide’ and ‘genocide blindness’. Contemp Polit Theory 13, 358–379 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1057/cpt.2013.48

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1057/cpt.2013.48

Keywords

Navigation