Skip to main content
Log in

Global Solidarity

  • Special Feature
  • Published:
Contemporary Political Theory Aims and scope

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Notes

  1. I was directed to this quote by Andrew Dobson in his recently published ‘Thick cosmopolitanism’, Political Studies 54 (2006), pp. 165–184, at p. 165.

  2. This list is certainly not definitive. Rather, it should be understood more as a compilation of the features most frequently described by scholars of solidarity as essential to the concept.

  3. It is sometimes suggested that solidarity can be understood in terms of identity. Jeff Spinner-Halev writes, for example, that a new democracy ‘needs a source of solidarity to motivate citizens, which it can obtain by codifying and appealing to national identity’. See his ‘Democracy, solidarity and post-nationalism’, Political Studies, (2008) 56/3: 604–628. However, solidarity is more often conceived as an alternative to identity as a cohesive force. See Ann Ferguson, ‘Global gender solidarity and feminist paradigms of justice’, paper presented to APSA Boston 2008, on file with author.

  4. Here one obvious objection is that shared values and goals do not exist even at the domestic level. I do not have the space to examine this objection here, but see Lea Ypi, ‘Political membership in the contractarian defense of cosmopolitanism’, Review of Politics 70/3 (2008), pp. 442–472 for more.

  5. This way of conceptualizing the source of trust is reported in, among others, Francis Fukuyama's Trust (New York: Free Press, 1995).

  6. 1 Rousseau expressed it well in his Social Contract: ‘The instant the People is legitimately assembled as a Sovereign body […] the person of the last Citizen is as sacred as that of the first Magistrate […]' (Rousseau, 1997, Book III, chapter 14, at p. 112).

  7. 2 One could wonder why we should distinguish the idea of equal moral worth from the concept of individual autonomy. To my mind, the answer lies with Mill : while the value of individual autonomy demands that we defend ‘experiments in living’ the equal moral worth we attribute to individuals may still allow for paternalistic policies that aim to prevent a person from harming herself by using drugs, say. Thanks to Lea Ypi for raising this point.

  8. 3 One other argument might be that we may rely on the mechanisms of reciprocity as part of society's welfare provision. I believe the reciprocity argument to fail, however, as it cannot account for provisions that will only ever benefit a very small but fragile portion of the population – think of homeless people – from whose needs a majority is firmly removed (see Barry, 1996).

  9. 4 There may be other constraints on individual autonomy and autonomous decision-making. For instance, we could imagine that certain options may be left off our horizon for cultural reasons. I might not imagine becoming a doctor if I was brought up to believe that my role is in the house (see Taylor, 1979). I am not concerned with these kinds of constraints here, although they may lead to conditions of vulnerability and thence from a liberal perspective, they should be cause for concern.

  10. 5 ‘Coercion is a technique for forcing people to act as the coercer wants them to act, and presumably contrary to their own preferences. It usually employs a threat of some dire consequence if the actor does not do what the coercer demands, although it is controversial whether a non-threatening offer might in some contexts be coercive' (Feinberg, 1998).

  11. 6 Some could argue that taking individual capabilities rather than individual vulnerability as the benchmark for autonomy might be better suited to address the motivation question. I believe, however, that in the case of the welfare state, emphasis on vulnerability is much more prominent than on capability. Since I build on the analogy with the welfare I have selected this approach as more relevant to my account. I thank one of the reviewer for pointing out this question.

  12. 7 There is, of course, quite a debate about what kind of institutions a just global order would call for (see Blake, 2001; Pogge, 2002). Regardless of what position one takes in that debate, it seems to me uncontroversial to say that we do not have international institutions akin to those we have in liberal welfare states, and which redistribute income systematically through the means of individual taxation and individual benefits. My thanks to one of the reviewers for helping me clarify this point.

References

  • Appiah, K.A. (2006) Cosmopolitanism: Ethics in a World of Strangers. New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bufacchi, V. (2005) Motivating justice. Contemporary Political Theory 4: 25–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dobson, A. (2006) Thick cosmopolitanism. Political Studies 54/1: 165–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Durkheim, E. (2006) On Suicide. New York: Penguin Books, (first published 1897).

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferguson, A. (2008) Global gender solidarity and feminist paradigms of justice. Paper presented to APSA Boston 2008, on file with author.

  • Francis Fukuyama. (1995) Trust. New York: Free Press.

  • Goodin, R. (1992) Motivating Political Morality. Oxford, UK: Blackwell Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, C. (2006) Self-determination beyond sovereignty: Relating transnational democracy to local autonomy. Journal of Social Philosophy 37/1: 44–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gould, C. (2007) Transnational solidarities. Journal of Social Philosophy 38/1: 148–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1990) Justice and solidarity: On the discussion concerning stage 6. In: T. Wren, W. Edelstein and G. Nunner-Winkler (eds.) The Moral Domain: Essays in the Ongoing Discussion between Philosophy and the Social Sciences. Boston, MA: MIT Press, pp. 224–254.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heyd, D. (2007) Justice and solidarity: The contractarian case against global justice. Journal of Social Philosophy 38/1: 112–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Linklater, A. (2006) Cosmopolitanism. In: A. Dobson and R. Eckersley (eds.) Political Theory and the Ecological Challenge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 109–128.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lu, C. (2000) The one and many faces of cosmopolitanism. Journal of Political Philosophy 8/2: 244–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meyer, L.H. (2000) Liberal cosmpolitanism and moral motivation. Global Society 14/4: 631–647.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. (1996) Patriotism and cosmopolitanism. In: J. Cohen (ed.) For Love of Country. Boston, MA: Beacon Press, pp. 3–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pensky, M. (2007) Two cheers for cosmopolitanism: Cosmopolitan solidarity as second-order inclusion. Journal of Social Philosophy 38/1: 165–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pogge, T. (2002) World Poverty and Human Rights. Oxford, UK: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheffler, S. (1992) Human Morality. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, J. (2007) From domestic to global solidarity: The dialectic of the particular and the universal in the building of social solidarity. Journal of Social Philosophy 38/1: 131–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shelby, T. (2002) Foundations of black solidarity: Collective identity or common oppression? Ethics 112: 231–266.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spinner-Halev, J. (2008) Democracy, solidarity and post-nationalism. Political Studies, 56/3, pp. 604–628.

  • Taylor, C. (1996) Why democracy needs patriotism. In: J. Cohen (ed.) For Love of Country. Boston, MA: Beacon Press, pp. 119–121.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas, L. (1988) Moral motivation: Kantians versus humans (and evolution). Midwest Studies in Philosophy 13: 367–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • White, S. (2002) Republicanism, patriotism and global justice. In: D. Bell and A. de Shalit (eds.) Forms of Justice. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, pp. 251–268.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ypi, L. (2008) Political membership in the contractarian defense of cosmopolitanism. Review of Politics 70/3: 442–472.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barry, B. (1990) The welfare state vs the relief of poverty. Ethics 100: 503–529.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barry, B. (1996) Nationalism vs liberalism? Nations and Nationalism 2: 460–465.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blake, M. (2001) Distributive justice, state coercion, and autonomy. Philosophy and Public Affairs 30 (3): 257–296.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brunkhorst, H. (2005) Solidarity. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Canovan, M. (1996) Nationhood and Political Theory. Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carens, J. (1986) The virtues of socialism. Theory and Society 15: 679–687.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Durkheim, E. (1964) The Division of Labour in Society. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. (1988) Harmless Wrongdoing. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. (1998) Coercion. In: E. Craig (ed.) Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. London: Routledge, http://www.rep.routledge.com/article/S007SECT1, accessed 23 March 2008.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodin, R.E. (1985a) Protecting the Vulnerable. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodin, R.E. (1985b) Vulnerabilities and responsibilities: An ethical defense of the welfare state. The American Political Science Review 79: 775–787.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodin, R.E. (1988) Reasons for Welfare. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H.L.A. (1967) Social solidarity and the enforcement of morals. The University of Chicago Law Review 35: 1–13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harvey, J. (2007) Moral solidarity and emphatic understanding: The moral value and scope of the relationship. Journal of Social Philosophy 38: 22–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Höffe, O. (1999) Demokratie im Zeitalter der Globalisierung. Munich, Germany: C.H.C. Beck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D. (2007) National Responsibility and Global Justice. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, O. (1998) Vulnerability and finitude. In: E. Craig (ed.) Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. London: Routledge, http://www.rep.routledge.com/article/L113SECT2, accessed 9 March 2008.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, O. (2001) Agents of justice. Metaphilosophy 32: 180–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pogge, T. (2002) World Poverty and Human Rights. Oxford, UK: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1986) The Morality of Freedom. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. (1989) Contingency, Irony and Solidarity. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, J.-J. (1997) The Social Contract and other Political Writings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheffler, S. (2001) Boundaries and Allegiances – Problems of Justice and Responsibility in Liberal Thought. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shue, H. (1988) Mediating duties. Ethics 98: 687–704.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. (1996) Why Democracy needs Patriotism. In: J. Cohen (ed.) For Love of Country. Boston, MA: Beacon Press, pp. 119–121.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. (1979) What's wrong with negative liberty. In: A. Ryan, (ed.) The Idea of Freedom. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wertheim, A. (2008) Exploitation. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (fall 2008 edition). In: Edward N. Zalta (ed.), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/exploitation/.

  • White, S. (2008) Social minimum. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (spring 2008 edition). In: Edward N. Zalta (ed.) http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2008/entries/social-minimum/.

  • Chilvers, I. (1998) A Dictionary of Twentieth-Century Art. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crawford, N.C. (2002) Argument and Change in World Politics: Ethics, Decolonization, and Humanitarian Intervention. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Della Porta, D., Kriesi, H., Rucht, D. (eds.) (1999) Social Movements in a Globalizing World. London: Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dobson, A. (2006) Thick cosmopolitanism. Political Studies 54: 165–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dryzek, J.S. (2002) Deliberative Democracy and Beyond – Liberals, Critics, Contestations. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Egbert, D.D. (1967) The idea of ‘avant-garde’ in art and politics. The American Historical Review 78: 339–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Finnemore, M. and Sikkink, K. (1998) International norm dynamics and political change. International Organization 52: 887–917.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodin, R.E. (1985) Protecting the Vulnerable: A Reanalysis of our Social Responsibilities. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gramsci, A. (1971) Selections from the Prison Notebooks. London: International Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobsbawm, E. (1999) Behind the Times: The Decline and Fall of the Twentieth-Century Avant-Gardes. New York: Thames and Hudson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keck, M. and Sikkink, K. (1998) Activists beyond borders: Advocacy networks in International Politics. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lenard, P.T. (2009) What's solidaristic about global solidarity? Contemporary Political Theory 8 (3).

  • Risse, T., Ropp, S. and Sikkink, K. (eds.) (1999) The Power of Human Rights: International Norms & Domestic Change. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H.D.S. ([1825] 1975) Selected Writings on Science, Industry and Social Organization. London: Croom Helm.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stears, M. (2005) The vocation of political theory: Principles, empirical inquiry and the politics of opportunity. European Journal of Political Theory 4: 325–350.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stears, M. (2009) Demanding Democracy: American Radicals in Search of a New Politics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Straehle, C. (2009) National and cosmopolitan solidarity. Contemporary Political Theory 8 (3).

  • Young, I.M. (2004) Responsibility and global labour justice. The Journal of Political Philosophy 12: 365–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ypi, L. (2008) Statist cosmopolitanism. Journal of Political Philosophy 16: 48–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding authors

Correspondence to Christine Straehle or Lea Ypi.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Tamara Lenard, P., Straehle, C. & Ypi, L. Global Solidarity. Contemp Polit Theory 9, 99–130 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1057/cpt.2009.9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1057/cpt.2009.9

Navigation