Skip to main content
Log in

The feasibility of an expanded regime on the use of force: the case of the responsibility to protect

  • Article
  • Published:
Journal of International Relations and Development Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article addresses the question of whether an expanded regime on the use of force, based on the report The Responsibility to Protect (R2P) of the International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty (ICISS) of 2001, would be feasible. The formula of the R2P has since found its way into the United Nations machinery via the final resolution from the World Summit in 2005 and can be seen as an emerging and more permissive norm on the use of force in cases of humanitarian catastrophes. The question of whether or not the theoretical framework of the norm is feasible is therefore urgent. Our analysis of feasibility is based on three logics of human action: the logic of consequence, logic of appropriateness and logic of arguing. We argue that each of these logics contains aspects that must be observed before a regime can be considered feasible. These logics are coupled with three mechanisms of socialisation of norms: strategic calculation, role-playing and normative suasion. We construct a minimal standard for a feasible regime by deducing requirements from the logics and their mechanisms, and then apply that standard to the content of the ICISS report. The empirical results show that the report must address the fact that it lacks qualities in regard to all three logics, before the expanded regime can be considered feasible.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. We are well aware that the status of R2P as a norm is disputed (e.g., Stahn 2007). However, we argue that it is reasonable to regard R2P as a norm. Following Barbour and Gorlick (2008: 535), we think that ‘its unanimous acceptance at the 2005 World Summit, and subsequent endorsement by both the UN General Assembly and Security Council, provides evidence of the widespread approval of R2P as a developing legal norm’ and that the ‘2005 World Summit Outcome document … demonstrated broad acceptance of a new norm referred to as the “Responsibility to Protect” ’. For a study on the advancement of this norm, see, for example, Thakur and Weiss (2009). See also Wheeler (2005), who describes the R2P as a new norm.

  2. However, the doctrine of ‘sovereignty as responsibility’, which forms the base for the moral imperative of ‘R2P’, can be traced to Francis M. Deng (Deng et al. 1996).

  3. The wording, ‘expanded regime on the use of force’ implies that we already have a regime on the use of force. This regime is based not only on Chapter 7 in the UN charter, but also on other charter provisions. One argument for why we claim that the international community could be said to move beyond this original regime relates to the question of right vs responsibility. While Chapter 7 is based on a right to use force in situations that threaten international peace and security, the R2P is literally based on a duty to react in certain situations. Since a duty to act in a certain way is stronger than a right to act, we would therefore see an expanded regime with a new normative base, compared with the existing regime on the use of force, if the full potential of the R2P were to be institutionalised. Until then, however, we can only talk of the R2P as a possible or emerging expansion of the already existing, but more limited, regime on the use of force.

  4. According to the political philosopher Kok-Chor Tan (2006: 84), relatively little attention has been paid to whether or not humanitarian intervention under some circumstances is obligatory. Rather, the question of the permissibility of such interventions has been at the centre of the debate (for overviews, see Smith 2006). Considering this, it is no surprise that the literature discussing the implications of the shift from a (possible) right to a duty to intervene on a general level is in an early phase and still limited (e.g., Bagnoli 2005; Tan 2006; Peters 2009) and that the literature specifically discussing the feasibility of this shift is more or less absent.

  5. Eclecticism in international relations is sometimes associated with the lack of coherence and sometimes even with incoherence. As the German constructivist Harald Müller (2004: 396) concludes: ‘Theories based on contradictory ontologies are incoherent’. However, we have no ambition to synthesise components from different theories; rather, our aim is to keep the three different logics of human actions separate in order to test the feasibility of a potentially expanded regime in an exhaustive way. Still, the mere fact that we do not exclude the logic of appropriateness and the logic of arguing implies that our framework is incompatible with a strict rationalistic perspective, and the mere fact that we do not exclude the logic of consequences implies that our framework is incompatible with thick constructivism. Nevertheless, this means that our approach is compatible with, as Thomas Risse (2000: 12) puts it, ‘sophisticated rational choice and moderate constructivism’.

  6. Her determinants of political feasibility, which are ‘discerned from the literature’, reflect this dependence on rational choice (Skodvin 2007: 2). However, this is not only limited to studies of feasibility; regime theory in general is ‘premised on rationalist assumptions’ (Checkel 1999: 84).

  7. It can be noted that Checkel does not explicitly connect normative suasion with the logic of arguing; rather, there are indications that he locates this mechanism in the realm of the logic of appropriateness (Checkel 2005: 812). However, he conceptualises the mechanism behind normative suasion in a manner that suits well the ‘logic of arguing’ (ibid.). See Pouliot (2008: 257–88) for a similar interpretation.

  8. In this article, the logic of bargaining is seen as an action within the logic of consequence; see, for example, Müller (2004: 396).

  9. It can be noted that Gallya Lahav (2004: 1158) explicitly justifies the relevance of examining public opinion with the argument of the logic of appropriateness.

  10. ‘ “[v]alidity claim” … refers to any claim that can be criticized and defended’ (Rehg 2005: 97).

  11. Admittedly, coherence and consistency are not synonymous in a technical sense. As Laurence Bonjour (1985) notes, consistency only implies adherence to the law of non-contradiction, which is obviously not sufficient for making an argument. However, coherence and consistency are sometimes used interchangeably (e.g., Haack 2004). According to us, this is the most appropriate way to interpret Risse, which is also illustrated when he applies his own assessments criteria (e.g., Ulbert and Risse 2005).

  12. For objections to the possibility of a common lifeworld, see, for example, Grobe (2010). Our claim of the existence of a universal ideal of coherence raises the question of whether our operationalisation of the logic of arguing in terms of coherence in fact results in a formalistic logic of appropriateness: only a coherent regime will be considered as appropriate. We will argue against such an interpretation. First of all, it must be noted that the ideal of coherence is substantively empty. This ideal is therefore a ‘criterialess criterion’ (Alexy 1998). It is substantively compatible with all kinds of ideas — as long as they are coherent. This obviously differs from ideals associated with the logic of appropriateness (e.g., March and Olsen 1998). Furthermore, in contrast to ideals of logic of appropriateness but in line with the logic of arguing, the ideal of coherence implies a conscious process of looking for the better argument. This also constitutes a line of demarcation between the ideal of coherence and the logic of appropriateness.

  13. However, as Neta C. Crawford (2002: 35–7) notes in Argument and Change in World Politics, other factors than the strength of the argument determine the efficiency of an argument. For example, the credibility of the arguer is important, as well as whether the arguer is being emotionally appealing or not (ibid.). However, the general and hypothetical nature of our approach makes it hard to consider those factors in our analysis.

  14. We have not found the distinction between incoherence within and between inferences, respectively, in the literature. However, this distinction corresponds to a large extent with the distinction between horizontal and vertical coherence, which is used in legal contexts (e.g., Vila 2001: 149–50). The distinction between incoherence within and between inferences is, however, narrower and therefore more precise than the one between vertical and horizontal coherence, since it explicates the nature of incoherence in terms of (lack of) inferential connections.

  15. The study includes 18 countries — China, India, the United States, Indonesia, Russia, France, Thailand, Ukraine, Poland, Iran, Mexico, South Korea, the Philippines, Australia, Argentina, Peru, Israel and Armenia — plus the Palestinian territories. Not all questions were asked in all countries.

  16. Information about the positions of the states before the World Summit 2005 also reveals a widespread scepticism towards the norm of R2P, particularly among Asian countries. A list of these positions has been collected by the organisation Reform the UN and can be downloaded from the following website: http://www.reformtheun.org/index.php?option=com_content&view=article&id=13&Itemid=56 (accessed 7 March, 2011).

References

  • Alexy, Robert (1998) ‘Coherence and Argumentation or the Genuine Twin Criteria less Super Criterion’, in Aulis Aarnio, Robert Alexy, Aleksander Peczenik, Wlodek Rabinowicz and Jan Wolenski, eds, On Coherence Theory of Law, 41–9, Lund: Juristförlaget i Lund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ayoob, Mohemmed (2002) ‘Humanitarian Intervention and State Sovereignty’, The International Journal of Human Rights 6 (1): 81–102.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bagnoli, Carla (2005) ‘Humanitarian Intervention as a Perfect Duty: A Kantian Argument’, Nomos 47 (1): 117–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barbour, Brian and Brian Gorlick (2008) ‘Embracing the “Responsibility to Protect”: A Repertoire of Measures Including Asylum for Potential Victims’, International Journal of Refugee Law 20 (4): 533–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron, Marcia (2005) ‘Justifications and Excuses’, Ohio State Journal of Criminal Law 2 (2): 387–405.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bellamy, Alex J. (2006) ‘Whither the Responsibility to Protect? Humanitarian Intervention and the 2005 World Summit’, Ethics & International Affairs 20 (2): 143–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bellamy, Alex J. (2009a) The Responsibility to Protect, Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bellamy, Alex J. (2009b) ‘Realizing the Responsibility to Protect’, International Studies Perspectives 10 (2): 111–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bellamy, Alex J. (2011) ‘The Responsibility to Protect: Libya and Beyond’, e-International Relations, 30 March, http://www.e-ir.info/?p=7912 (accessed 26 June, 2011).

  • Bjola, Corneliu (2005) ‘Legitimating the Use of Force in International Politics: A Communicative Action Perspective’, European Journal of International Relations 11 (2): 266–303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bonjour, Laurence (1985) The Structure of Empirical Knowledge, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brommesson, Douglas and Henrik Friberg Fernros (2009) ‘Individualisation and Destabilization of the International Order: The Case of the Responsibility to Protect’, International Review of Sociology 19 (2): 315–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, Allen (2006) ‘Institutionalizing the Just War’, Philosophy and Public Affairs 34 (1): 2–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buzan, Barry (2001) ‘The English School: An Underexploited Resource in IR’, Review of International Studies 27 (3): 471–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Checkel, Jeffrey (1999) ‘Norms, Institutions, and National Identity in Contemporary Europe’, International Studies Quarterly 43 (1): 83–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Checkel, Jeffrey (2005) ‘International Institutions and Socialization in Europe: Introduction and Framework’, International Organization 59 (4): 801–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chesterman, Simon (2011) ‘Leading from Behind: The Responsibility to Protect, the Obama Doctrine, and Humanitarian Intervention After Libya’, Ethics and International Affairs 25 (3): 279–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crawford, Neta (2002) Argument and Change in World Politics: Ethics, Decolonization, and Humanitarian Intervention, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Deng, Francis M., Donald Rothchild, William Zartman, Sadikiel Kimaro and Terrence Lyons (1996) Sovereignty as Responsibility: Conflict Management in Africa, Washington DC: The Brookings Institution.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dickson, Julie (2010) ‘Interpretation and Coherence in Legal Reasoning’, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/legal-reas-interpret (accessed 12 April, 2012).

  • Dworkin, Ronald (1986) Law's Empire, Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Etzioni, Amitai (2006) ‘Sovereignty as Responsibility’, Orbis 50 (1): 71–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, Gareth (2011) ‘The Responsibility to Protect Libyans’, Project Syndicate, 27 February, http://www.project-syndicate.org/commentary/evans3/English (accessed 26 June, 2011).

  • Evans, Jonathan St. (2008) ‘Reasoning, Decision Making’, in Jonathan Adler and Lance J. Rips, eds, Reasoning: Studies of Human Inference and Its Foundation, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fearon, James and Alexander Wendt (2002) ‘Rationalism v Constructivism: A Skeptical View’, in Walter Carlsnaes, Thomas Risse and Beth Simmons, eds, Handbook of International Relations, 52–72, London: Sage Publications.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Franck, Thomas M. (1990) The Power of Legitimacy among Nations, New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friberg Fernros, Henrik (2008) I gränslandet till liv och död. Om människovärdet och den offentliga maktens koherens [In the Borderland between Life and Death: On Human Value and the Coherence of Public Power], Göteborg: Department of Political Science.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grobe, Christian (2010) ‘The Power of Words: Argumentative Persuasion in International Negotiations’, European Journal of International Relations 16 (1): 5–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haack, Susan (2004) ‘Coherence, Consistency, Cogency, Congruity, Cohesiveness, &c.: Remain Calm! Don’t Go Overboard!’, New Literary History 35 (2): 167–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen (1984) The Theory of Communicative Action: Reason and the Rationalization of Society, Boston: Beacon Press COP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Human Rights Center (2007) The Responsibility to Protect (R2P): Moving the Campaign Forward, Berkeley: International Human Rights Law Clinic, University of California.

  • ICISS (2001) The Responsibility to Protect, Ottawa: International Development Research Centre.

  • Johnson-Laird, P.N. (1999) ‘Deductive Reasoning’, Annual Review of Psychology 50 (1): 109–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keohane, Robert (1989) ‘International Institutions: Two Approaches’, in Robert Keohane, ed., International Institutions and State Power, 158–79, Boulder: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ki-moon, Ban (2011) ‘Secretary-General Says that Security Council Action on Libya Affirms International Community's Determination to Protect Civilians from own Government's Violence’, Department of Public Information, UN, http://www.un.org/News/Press/docs/2011/sgsm13454.doc.htm (accessed 26 June, 2011).

  • Krasner, Stephen D. (1983) International Regimes, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krasner, Stephen D. (1999) Sovereignty: Organized Hypocrisy, Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Laegaard, Sune (2006) ‘Feasibility and Stability in Normative Political Philosophy: The Case of Liberal Nationalism’, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 9 (4): 399–416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lahav, Gallya (2004) ‘Public Opinion Toward Immigration in the European Union’, Comparative Political Studies 37 (10): 1151–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lepard, Brian (2002) Rethinking Humanitarian Intervention: A Fresh Legal Approach Based on Fundamental Ethical Principles in International Law and World Religions, University Park: Pennsylvania University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lerch, Marika and Guido Schwellnus (2006) ‘Normative by Nature? The Role of Coherence in Justifying the EU External Human Rights Policy’, Journal of European Policy 13 (2): 304–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Makinda, Samuel M. (2000) ‘International Society and Eclecticism in International Relations Theory’, Cooperation and Conflict 35 (2): 205–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • March, James G. and Johan P. Olsen (1998) ‘The Institutional Dynamics of International Political Orders’, International Organization 52 (4): 729–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meltsner, Arnold (1972) ‘Political Feasibility and Policy Analysis’, Public Administration Review 32 (6): 859–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miles, Edward L., Arild Underdal, Steinar Andresen, Jorgen Wettestad, Jon Birger Skjaerseth and Elaine M. Carlin (2002) Environmental Regime Effectiveness: Confronting Theory with Evidence, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, Ronald B. (2009) International Politics and the Environment, Los Angeles: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller, Harald (2004) ‘Arguing, Bargaining and All That: Communicative Action, Rationalist Theory and the Logic of Appropriateness in International Relations’, European Journal of International Relations 10 (3): 395–435.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nisbett, Richard E. and Ara Norenzayan (2002) ‘Culture and Cognition’, in Hal Pashler, ed., Stevens’ Handbook of Experimental Psychology, 3rd edn., New York: John Wiley and Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Permanent Mission of the Russian Federation to the United Nations (2007) ‘Position of Russia at the Sixty-First Session of the UN General Assembly, http://www.un.int/russia/new/MainRoot/docs/interview/060831indexen.htm (accessed 20 December, 2008).

  • Perrin, Sophie and Thomas Bernauer (2010) ‘International Regime Formation Revisited: Explaining Ratification Behaviour with Respect to Long-range Transboundary Air Pollution Agreements in Europe’, European Union Politics 11 (3): 405–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peters, Anne (2009) ‘Humanity as the A and [omega] of Sovereignty’, European Journal of International Law 20 (3): 513–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peters, Guy (1999) Institutional Theory in Political Science: The New Institutionalism, London: Continuum International Publishing Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinto, Robert C. (2001) Argument, Inference and Dialectic: Collected Papers on Informal Logic, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pouliot, Vincent (2008) ‘The Logic of Practicality: A Theory of Practice of Security Communities’, International Organization 62 (2): 257–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raz, Joseph (1994) Ethics in the Public Domain: Essays in the Morality of Law and Politics, Oxford: Clerendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rehg, William (2005) ‘Assessing the Cogency of Arguments: Three Kinds of Merits’, Informal Logic 25 (2): 95–115.

    Google Scholar 

  • Risse, Thomas (2000) ‘Let's Argue! — Communicative Action in World Politics’, International Organization 54 (1): 1–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shaw, Victoria F. (1996) ‘The Cognitive Processes in Informal Reasoning’, Thinking and Reasoning 2 (1): 51–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skodvin, Tora (2007) ‘Exploring the Notion of Political Feasibility in Environmental Policy’, Cicero Working Paper 2007:03.

  • Smith, Michael J. (2006) ‘Humanitarian Intervention: An Overview of the Ethical Issues’, Ethics & International Affairs 12 (1): 63–79.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stahn, Carsten (2007) ‘Responsibility to Protect: Political Rhetoric or Emerging Legal Norm?’ The American Journal of International Law 101 (1): 99–120.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stamnes, Eli (2009) ‘“Speaking R2P” and the Prevention of Mass Atrocities’, Global Responsibility to Protect 1 (1): 70–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tan, Kok-Chor (2006) ‘The Duty to Protect’, in Terry Nardin and Melissa S. Williams, eds, Humanitarian Intervention, New York: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thakur, Ramesh (2011) ‘UN Breathes Life into “Responsibility to Protect”’, Thestar.com, March 21, http://www.thestar.com/opinion/editorialopinion/article/957664--un-breathes-life-into-responsibility-to-protect (accessed 26 June, 2011).

  • Thakur, Ramesh and Thomas G. Weiss (2009) ‘R2P: From Idea to Norm — and Action?’ Global Responsibility to Protect 1 (1): 22–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • The Economist (2006) ‘Sudan: Catastrophe Looms — Averting it Requires Help, Most of All from China’, 9 September: 13.

  • Traub, James (2006) ‘The World According to China’, New York Times Magazine, 3 September: 24−9.

  • Ulbert, Cornelia and Thomas Risse (2005) ‘Deliberately Changing the Discourse: What Does Make Arguing Effective?’ Acta Politica 40 (3): 351–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • United Nations (2009) ‘Implementation of the Responsibility to Protect — Report of the Secretary-General’, A/63/677, 12 January, New York.

  • United Nations Security Council (2007) ‘Open Debate on the Protection of Civilians in Armed Conflict’, 22 June, http://www.responsibilitytoprotect.org/index.php/pages/1285 (accessed 20 December, 2008).

  • United Nations Security Council (2011) ‘Resolution 1973’, 17 March, New York.

  • United Nations World Summit (2005) ‘General Assembly Resolution 2005’, A/RES/60/1, 24 October, New York.

  • Vila, Marisa I. (2001) Facing Judicial Discretion: Legal Knowledge and Right Answer Revisited, Dortrecht: Kluwer Academic Publisher.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Washington Post (2006) ‘Responsible China? Darfur Exposes Chinese Hypocrisy’, 6 September, http://www.washingtonpost.com/wp-dyn/content/article/2006/09/05/AR2006090501187.html (accessed 11 April, 2012).

  • Wheeler, Nicholas J. (2005) A Victory for Common Humanity? The Responsibility to Protect after the 2005 World Summit. Paper presented at the conference ‘The UN at Sixty: Celebration or Wake’, 6–7 October, Toronto.

  • Wheeler, Nicholas J. and Frazer Egerton (2009) ‘The Responsibility to Protect: “Precious Commitment” or a Promise Unfilled?’ Global Responsibility to Protect 1 (1): 114–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiener, Antje (2007) ‘The Dual Quality of Norms and Governance beyond the State: Sociological and Normative Approaches to “Interaction”’, Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 10 (1): 47–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • World Public Opinion (2007) ‘Publics around the World say UN has Responsibility to Protect againstGenocide’, http://www.worldpublicopinion.org/pipa/pdf/apr07/CCGA+_Genocide_article.pdf.

  • Young, Oran R. (1994) International Governance: Protecting the Environment in a Stateless Society, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We want to express our gratitude to the Swedish Research Council for a generous grant that made the research reported in this article possible. We are furthermore grateful for excellent comments from the reviewers and the editorial team of JIRD together with several colleagues at the Department of Political Science at University of Gothenburg, the School of Social Sciences at Linnaeus University and various discussants at conferences where we have presented earlier drafts of this article.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Brommesson, D., Fernros, H. The feasibility of an expanded regime on the use of force: the case of the responsibility to protect. J Int Relat Dev 16, 138–166 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1057/jird.2012.9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1057/jird.2012.9

Keywords

Navigation