Skip to main content
Log in

Beyond Newspeak: three arguments for the persistence of the informal in the creation and use of computational ontologies

  • Article
  • Published:
Knowledge Management Research & Practice

Abstract

The creation and use of computational ontologies that represent a wide variety of information sources has been an assumed necessity for communication on the Semantic Web. Embedded in this necessity comes the challenge of to codify or to collaborate. The codify view fits very well with an objectivist view of knowledge management and with the current use of computational ontologies as an engineering artifact. The collaborate view, is more aligned with a philosophical view of ontology, mostly from a hermeneutical perspective based on the work of Heidegger. Computational ontologies are limited by the condition of consistency and work well on communication within a single perspective. On the other hand, ontology from a hermeneutical perspective is explicitly useful in speaking across perspectives. The view that we hold in this paper is that both are important and complementary to each other. We frame our discussion of to codify or to collaborate in terms the Tower of Babel problem and the ensuing Newspeak solution. The need to allow multiple, and sometimes incompatible, models to coexist leads to the Tower of Babel problem. A solution to this problem would be the creation of a new language, simpler and less capable of expressing different perspectives, Newspeak. We also give an explanation of the importance of the tacit in all communication and we give three arguments for the persistence of the informal. We conclude that the process of reflective reasoning described here is the context in play when in the appropriate use of consistent computational ontologies, as well as being the foundation of collaborative communicative enterprises.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Alonso-Jimenez JA, Borrego-Diaz J, Chavez-Gonzalez AM and Martin-Mateos FJ (2006) Foundational challenges in automated data and ontology cleaning in the semantic web. IEEE Intelligent Systems 21 (1), 42–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bell D (1999) The Coming of Post-Industrial Society: A Venture in Social Forecasting. Basic Books, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collingwood RG (1959) An Autobiography. Oxford University Press, London; New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collingwood RG (1963) Speculum Mentis: Or, The Map of Knowledge. Clarendon press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus H (1991) Being-in-the-World: A commentary on Heidegger's Being and Time, Division I. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus H (1993) Heidegger on the connection between nihilism, art, technology, and politics. In The Cambridge Companion to Heidegger (GUIGNON CB, Ed), pp 345–372, Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK; New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gadamer H-G (2003) Truth and Method (Original publication 1960, as Wahrheit und Methode). The Continuum Publishing Company, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guarino N (1998) Formal ontology and information systems. In Formal Ontology in Information Systems (GUARINO N, Ed), pp 3–18 IOS Press, Amsterdam, Netherlands.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger M (1962) Being and Time. Harper, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger M (1971) Poetry, Language, Thought. Harper & Row, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger M (1997) Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics. Indiana University Press, Bloomington, Indiana.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hunter A (2003) Evaluating significance of inconsistencies. In The International Joint Conference on AI - IJCAI’03. (Gottlob G and Walsh T, Eds), pp 468–478, Morgan Kaufmann, Acapulco, Mexico.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1996) Critique of Pure Reason. Hackett Publishing Company, Indianapolis, IN.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn TS (1996) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos I (1970) Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes. In Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge (LAKATOS I and MUSGRAVE A, Eds), pp 91–196, University Press, Cambridge, England.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos I and Musgrave A (1970) Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge. University Press, Cambridge, England.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ma Y, Qi G, Hitzler P and Lin Z (2007) Measuring inconsistency for description logics based on paraconsistent semantics. Lecture Notes in Computer Science 4724, 4730.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin J and Davenport D (1999) Noncomputational versus computational conceptions of reason: Contrasting educational implications. Bulletin of Science, Technology & Society 19 (1), 25–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nonaka I (1991) The knowledge-creating company. Harvard Business Review 69 (6), 96–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nonaka I (1994) A dynamic theory of organisational knowledge creation, organization science. Organization Science 5 (1), 14–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nonaka I and Takeuchi H (1995) The Knowledge Creating Company: How Japanese Companies Create the Dynamics of Innovation. Oxford University Press, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi M (1958) Personal Knowledge; Towards a Post-Critical Philosophy. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi M (1966) The Tacit Dimension. Doubleday, Garden City, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi M (1974) Scientific Thought and Social Reality: Essays. International Universities Press, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi M and Grene MG (1969) Knowing and Being: Essays. Routledge & K. Paul, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper KR (2002) The Logic of Scientific Discovery. Routledge, London; New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam H (1988) Representation and Reality. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith B (2003) Ontology. In The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Computing and Information (FLORIDI L, Ed), pp 155–166, Blackwell, Malden, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sørensen C and Snis U (2000) Codify or collaborate? In IRIS 23. Laboratorium for Interaction Technology, University of Trollhättan (SVENSSON L, SNIS U, SØRENSEN C, FÄGERLIND H, LINDROTH T, MAGNUSSON M, Östlund C, Eds), Uddevalla, Sweden.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tarski A and Tarski J (1994) Introduction to Logic and to the Methodology of the Deductive Sciences. Oxford University Press, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tsoukas H (2003) Do we really understand tacit knowledge? In The Blackwell Handbook of Organizational Learning and Knowledge (EASTERBY-SMITH M and LYLES MA, Eds), pp 410–427, Blackwell Publishers, Malden, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsham G (2005). Knowledge Management Systems: Representation and Communication in Context. Systems, Signs & Actions, 1, 6–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitehead AN and Russell B (1997) Principia Mathematica. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK; New York.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Frederico Fonseca.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Fonseca, F., Martin, J. Beyond Newspeak: three arguments for the persistence of the informal in the creation and use of computational ontologies. Knowl Manage Res Pract 7, 196–205 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1057/kmrp.2009.16

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1057/kmrp.2009.16

Keywords

Navigation