Skip to main content
Log in

Intertemporal pricing with boundedly rational consumers

  • Research Article
  • Published:
Journal of Revenue and Pricing Management Aims and scope

Abstract

Flexible pricing plans are commonly observed in service industries. In this article, we argue that the presence of flexible pricing plans can be attributed to consumers being boundedly rational – these consumers do not always select the best available option; rather, they select better options more often. In our model, the seller faces consumers who are heterogeneous in their degrees of intertemporal inconsistency – their ultimate actions can be different from their intended actions. We show that, in response to these boundedly rational consumers the seller may be able to extract more profit by setting different prices in different periods and allowing the consumers to self-select which period to pay. Moreover, a single pricing plan may emerge as an optimal pricing scheme even when the consumers are heterogeneous in their degrees of rationality and the seller is not fully aware of the consumers’ types. We further show that the pricing patterns depend primarily on the relative discounting factor between the seller and the consumers.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Figure 1
Figure 2
Figure 3
Figure 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Flexible pricing is commonly adopted by conference organizers. As an another example, the 2009 INFORMS conference on O.R. practice has an early registration deadline, 10 April. Participants who register before the deadline pays $970 while participants who register after it pays $1070. Moreover, INFORMS members enjoy a $100 discount, that is they pay $870 to register before the deadline and $970 to register after it.

  2. We thank an anonymous reviewer for this suggestion.

  3. We now give an example to show that our model is suitable for competitors who order different pricing strategies as well as services that consumers value differently. Suppose there are three competitors (A, B and C) whose services are valued by consumers as μa, μb and μc respectively. Competitor A sells the service only in the first period at price pa1 while Competitor B sells the service only in the second period at price p2b. Competitor C, on the other hand, offers a pricing plan {p1c, p2c}. For a type-i consumer, her utility from accepting Competitor A's order is μap1a and that from Competitor B's order is μbδ c p2b. The consumer's expected utility from accepting Competitor C's offer is (μcp1c) × q1+(μcδ c p2c) × q2, where and q2=1−q1. Thus, the best outside option (μi0) is type-dependent and in this example equals to the maximum of the three (expected) utilities.

  4. The derivation of the equation is shown below:

  5. The derivation of the second-order derivative is as follows:

References

  • Anderson, S., Goeree, J. and Holt, C. (1998) Rent seeking with bounded rationality: An analysis of the all-pay auction. Journal of Political Economy 106 (4): 828–853.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bansal, M. and Maglaras, C. (2009) Dynamic pricing when customers strategically time their purchase: Asymptotic optimality of a two-price policy. Journal of Revenue & Pricing Management 85 (1): 15–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benabou, R. and Tirole, J. (2009, May) Over my dead body: Bargaining and the price of dignity. American Economic Review 99 (2): 459–465.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burnetas, P., Gilbert, S. and Smith, C. (2007) Quantity discounts in single-period supply contracts with asymmetric demand information. IIE Transactions 39: 465–479.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cachon, G. and Zhang, F. (2006) Procuring fast delivery: Sole-sourcing with information asymmetry. Management Science 52: 881–896.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chaturvedi, A. and Martínez-de-Albéniz, V. (2009) Optimal procurement design in the presence of supply risk. Manufacturing & Service Operations Management, advance online publication 18 February 2011, doi: 10.1287/msom.1100.0319.

  • Chen, K. and Hogg, T. (2009) Modeling risky economic decision-making with bounded rationality. forthcoming in the Proceedings of AAAI Spring Symposium 2009 Human Behavior Modeling.

  • Corbett, C. and de Groote, X. (2000) A supplier's optimal quantity discount policy under asymmetric information. Management Science 46: 444–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DellaVigna, S. (2009) Psychology and economics: Evidence from the field. Journal of Economic Literature 47 (2): 315–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DellaVigna, S. and Malmendier, U. (2004) Contract design and self-control: Theory and evidence. The Quarterly Journal of Economics 119 (2): 353–402.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deshpande, V., Schwarz, L., Atallah, M., Blanton, M. and Frikken, K. (2011) Outsourcing manufacturing: Secure price-masking mechanisms for purchasing component parts. Production and Operations Management 20 (2): 165–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eliaz, K. and Spiegler, R. (2007) A mechanism-design approach to speculative trade. Econometrica 75 (3): 875–884.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Filiz-Ozbay, E. (2008) Incorporating Unawareness into Contract Theory. Working paper, University of Maryland.

  • Gul, F. and Pesendorfer, W. (2001, November) Temptation and self-control. Econometrica 69 (6): 1403–1435.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ha, A. (2001) Supplier-buyer contracting: Asymmetric cost information and cutoff level policy for buyer participation. Naval Research Logistics 48: 41–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Han, S., Gupta, S. and Lehmann, D. (2001) Consumer price sensitivity and price thresholds. Journal of Retailing 77 (4): 435–456.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heifetz, A., Meier, M. and Schipper, B. (2009) Dynamic Unawareness and Rationalizable Behavior. Working paper, The Open University of Israel.

  • Iyer, A., Schwarz, L. and Zenios, S. (2005) A principal-agent model for product specification and production. Management Science 51: 106–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kostamis, D., Beil, D. and Duenyas, I. (2009) Total-cost procurement auctions: Impact of suppliers’ cost adjustments on auction format choice. Management Science 55 (12): 1985–1999.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koszegi, B. and Rabin, M. (2006, November) A model of reference-dependent preferences. The Quarterly Journal of Economics 121 (4): 1133–1165.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laffont, J. and Martimort, D. (2002) The Theory of Incentives: The Principal-Agent Model. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laffont, J. and Tirole, J. (1990) Adverse selection and renegotiation in procurement. The Review of Economic Studies 57 (4): 597–625.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lim, N. and Ho, T. (2007) Designing price contracts for boundedly rational customers: Does the number of blocks matter? Marketing Science 26 (3): 312–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKelvey, R. and Palfrey, T. (1995) Quantal response equilibria for normal form games. Games and Economic Behavior 10 (1): 6–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O'Donoghue, T. and Rabin, M. (1999) Incentives for procrastinators. Quarterly Journal of Economics 114: 769–816.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O'Donoghue, T. and Rabin, M. (2008) Procrastination on long-term projects. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 66: 161–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orhun, A. (2009) Optimal product line design when consumers exhibit choice set-dependent preferences. Marketing Science 28 (5): 868–886.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ozbay, E.Y. (2006) Unawareness and strategic announcements in games with uncertainty. International Journal of Game Theory 4: 1029–1050.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ozdenoren, E., Salant, S. and Silverman, D. (2006) Willpower and the Optimal Control of Visceral Urges. NBER Working Paper.

  • Rabin, M. (1998) Psychology and economics. Journal of Economic Literature 36 (1): 11–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubinstein, A. (1993) On price recognition and computational complexity in a monopolistic model. Journal of Political Economy 101 (3): 473–484.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Su, X. (2008) Bounded rationality in newsvendor models. Manufacturing & Service Operations Management 10 (4): 566–589.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, T. and Xiao, W. (2010) Does a manufacturer benefit from selling to a better-forecasting retailer? Management Science 56 (9): 1584–1598.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tirole, J. (2009) Cognition and incomplete contracts. American Economic Review 99 (1): 265–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Thadden, E. and Zhao, X. (2009) Incentives for Unaware Agents. Technical report, University of Mannheim (mimeo).

  • Wan, Z. and Beil, D. (2009) RFQ auctions with supplier qualification screening. Operations Research 57 (4): 934–949.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yang, Z., Aydin, G., Babich, V. and Beil, D. (2009) Supply disruptions, asymmetric information, and a backup production option. Management Science 55 (2): 192–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zhang, H. and Zenios, S. (2008) A dynamic principal-agent model with hidden information: Sequential optimality through truthful state revelation. Operations Research 56 (3): 681–696.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zhou, S.X., Tao, Z., Zhang, N.B. and Cai, G. (2009) Reverse Auction Procurement with Flexible Noncompetitive Contracts. Working paper, Chinese University of Hong Kong.

Download references

Acknowledgements

We thank Ian Yeoman (the editor) and the review team for their detailed comments and many valuable suggestions that have significantly improved the quality of the article. We also benefited from the discussions with Qian Liu, George Shanthikumar, Zuo-Jun Max Shen, Xuanming Su and Xiaojian Zhao. All remaining errors are our own.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Additional information

2joined the IEOR Department at UC Berkeley after completing his PhD in Operations Management from New York University. He also holds master's and bachelor's degrees of Electrical Engineering from National Taiwan University. He is a recipient of NYU teaching excellence award, Second place of INFORMS JFIG paper competition, the Harold MacDowell Award from Stern School, Meritorious Service Awards from Management Science and MSOM. His current research interests lie in operations-marketing interface, auctions, supply chain management and competitive strategies.

APPENDIX

APPENDIX

Proofs of Propositions 1, 2 and 3

Recall that the participation constraint can be written as

which, after replacing ui2 by v i +ui1, can be simplified as follows: . The seller's problem is therefore to find a pricing plan that solves the following problem:

Since ui2=v i +ui1 and δ s pi2=δ(pi1v i ), for a fixed value of v i , ui2 decreases as ui1 decreases and pi2 increases in pi1. Suppose that the participation constraint does not bind, the seller can decrease ui1 while keeping v i unchanged. ui2 decreases as a result. Since pi1=μui1 and pi2=(μui2)/δ c , both pi1 and pi2 increase and so does the seller's expected profit. Thus (PC-i) binds:

We can therefore represent utilities and prices in terms of v i :

Substituting these terms in the seller's objective, the seller's optimization problem becomes an unconstrained one:

where the third equation follows from . The first-order condition on v i leads to

Let and observe that D(0)=0 and D(v i ) is negative for all other values of v i . Therefore, and thus:

  • When δ=1, (A.2) is satisfied for any v i , thus the seller's expected profit is μc regardless of the first and second period prices.

  • When δ<1 and γ i >1/μ, first order derivative with respect to v i is positive for all values of v i . Thus the optimal value of v i is −∞, the optimal pricing plan is {pi1F, pi2F}={μ,∞}, and the associated seller's expected profit is μc.

  • When δ>1 and γ i >1/μ, first order derivative with respect to v i is negative for all values of v i . Thus the optimal value of v i is ∞, the optimal pricing plan is {pi1F, pi2F}={∞, δμ}, and the associated seller's expected profit is δμc.

Notice that D(v i ) is symmetric with respect to the origin:

Its derivative,

is negative for positive values of v i and positive for negative values of v i . Thus, for all γ i <1/μ, there are exactly two solutions to (A.2). Let v i P>0 be the positive solution and v i N=−v i P be the negative solution to (A.2). Now we examine the second-order conditions on v i :

We see that (A.3) is negative when δ<1 and positive when δ>1 while (A.4) is negative when δ>1 and positive when δ<1. Thus v i P is a local maximizer when δ<1 while v i N is a local maximizer when δ>1. We now show that Π i F monotonically decreases in γ i :

Thus, there exists a cutoff type, γ lp , such that the corresponding v lp (>0) satisfy Π i F(v lp )=μc. When δ<1, v i P is the global maximizer for all γ i <γ lp . we now look for the condition for γ lp and v lp :

Thus, γ lp and v lp satisfy the following equations simultaneously:

Similarly, there exists a cutoff type, γ mp , such that the corresponding v mp (<0) satisfy Π i F(v mp )=δμc. When δ>1, γ mp is the global maximizer for all γ i <γ mp ,

Thus, γ mp and v mp satisfy the following equations simultaneously:

Proof of Proposition 5

First, we re-write the optimization problem as

Notice that when δ<1, the {pi1, pi2}={μ,∞}, ∀i=1,2, is a feasible solution to (A.7). The seller's expected profit associated with this candidate solution is μc. We thus focus on searching for a solution that yields an expected profit that is higher than μc. Similarly, {pi1, pi2}={∞, δμ}, ∀i=1,2, is a feasible solution to (A.7) when δ>1. The seller's expected profit associated with this candidate solution is δμc, and we search for a solution that yields a higher than δμc expected profit. We now show that both (PC-2) and (IC-1,2) bind at optimality by contradiction. Suppose (PC-2): does not bind. In this case, the seller can increase his expected profit by decreasing u21 and u22 while keeping v2 unchanged (v2=u22u21). This will increase the objective value without violating any constraint. Thus (PC-2) binds, that is

Given this, we can write type-2 consumers’ utilities and payments in terms of a single variable v2:

We then consider (IC-1,2):

This constraint must bind at optimality as well; otherwise, the seller can increase his expected profit by decreasing u11 and u12 while keeping v2 unchanged. When v2>0, and thus When v2<0, and thus (IC-1,2) can then be written as the following equality constraint:

In the remaining proof, we divide our analysis into two cases: (1) v2 is positive and (2) v2 is negative. There are two subcases in each case: max{u11, u12}=u11 and max{u11, u12}=u12 in each case. We now look at each of them separately:

Case 1: v2 is positive.

Subcase 1.1: . In this case, A fully rational consumer purchases in the period when the price is lower, and thus the first-period price has to be non-negative in the optimal solution; otherwise, the seller can set the second-period price to be negative instead to obtain a smaller loss. Thus, p11⩾0, that is Notice that if we set v1=v2, we obtain u11=u12v1=u12v2=u22v2=u21. In this case,

that is, (IC-2,1) is satisfied. The seller's expected profit function can be written as an unconstrained optimization function with a single variable (v2):

First, let us compare the seller's expected profit with μc – obtained from a candidate solution {pi1, pi2}={μ,∞}, ∀i=1,2, when δ<1:

where the inequality follows from the fact that p11⩾0 and δ<1. Since , setting the first-period price to is never optimal when δ<1. Next, we compare the seller's expected profit with δμ−c – obtained from a candidate solution {pi1, pi2}={∞, δμ} when δ>1:Footnote 4

Thus, it is optimal to set v2 to infinity when the first-period price to

Subcase 1.2: In this case, Moreover, (PC-1):

is satisfied as well. Substituting all the utilities and payments by the aforementioned functions of v2, the seller's expected profit function can be written as:

Observe that when δ>1,

Since ΠS−(δμc)<0, it is optimal to set v2 to ∞. When δ<1, (A.8) is greater than equation (A.9) and in which case setting the second-period price to is never optimal. When δ<1 and the first-order condition on v2 yields

We can rewrite (A.10) as follows:

Let v2P be the positive solution of (A.11), the second-order condition is as followsFootnote 5:

The equation above is only negative when ρ1 is sufficiently small, that is if

we obtain that

The equation above shows that ΠS monotonically decreases in γ i .

Case 2: v2 is negative.

Subcase 2.1: With the same reasoning as Subcase 1.1, The seller's expected profit function can be written as

Let us first compare the seller's expected profit with μc – obtained from a candidate solution {pi1, pi2}={μ,∞}∀ i=1,2 when δ<1:

Therefore, setting the second-period price v2 to −∞ is optimal. We now compare the seller's expected profit with δμc, which is obtained from the candidate solution {pi1, pi2}={∞, δμ}, ∀ i=1, 2 when δ>1:

Thus, setting first-period price to is never optimal.

Subcase 2.2: In this case, The seller's optimization problem can be written as

Observe that when δ<1,

Thus, setting the second-period price v2 to −∞ is optimal. When δ>1, The expression of ΠS in (A.12) is greater than that in (A.13) and Therefore, setting the second-period price to is never optimal. When δ>1 and the first-order condition on v2 yields:

We can re-write (A.14) as

Let v2N be the negative solution of equation (A.15), the second-order condition is as follows:

Equation (A.16) is negative when ρ1 is sufficiently small. Specifically,

We now show that ΠS monotonically decreases in γ i :

Finally, we can pin down the cutoff thresholds ρ1c and vc. They are the solutions that solve (A.17) and (A.18) for δ<1:

and for δ>1:

Proof of Proposition 6

Since ui2=ui1+v i , (PC-i) and (IC-i, j) can be simplified as follows:

Now we show that (PC-2) and (IC-1,2) imply (PC-1):

Recall that both (PC-2) and (IC-1,2) bind, otherwise the seller can raise prices to decrease consumers’ utilities until they bind while increasing his expected profit. Define a positive function for all values of v. From the binding (PC-2) and (IC-1,2), we obtain that

Recall that the objective function is

After substituting the prices and utilities by functions of {v i }'s, we can express the reduced program of the seller's optimization problem as follows:

ΠS can then be written as follows:

Let

represent the maximum expected profit extracted from type-1 consumer when the seller is able to identify the consumer's type. Recall that γ c is the cutoff value of γ above which the seller's expected profit is bounded above by μc. Thus, R1*μc for all γ1γ c . Since F(v2)⩾0 for all values of v2,

Similarly, let

represent the maximum revenue extracted from type-2 consumer when the consumer's type is known. Since γ2<γ c , R2*>μ. From the above discussions, we obtain an upper bound of the excess expected profit the seller can obtain from offering a menu of contracts:

Notice that when ρ1=1, only type-1 consumers are present in the market. ΠS becomes ΠF and thus ΠS=μc. When ρ1=0, ΠS=R2*>μc.

Let and be the cutoff value such that For any value of Thus, it is optimal for the seller to simply offer a single pricing plan {pi1, pi2}={μ, ∞}. □

Proof of Proposition 7

The participation constraint can be simplified as

This constraint must bind, thus we can re-write utilities and prices in terms of v i :

Substituting these terms in the seller's objective, the seller's optimization problem becomes an unconstrained one:

The first-order condition on v i leads to

Notice that the above equation is the same as equation (A.2) in the basic case if we replace μμi0 by μ. Thus, we can directly borrow results from the proofs of Propositions 1, 2 and 3:

  • When δ=1, equation (A.19) is satisfied for any v i , thus the seller's expected profit is μμi0c regardless of the first and second period prices.

  • When δ<1 and γ i >1/μμi0, first-order derivative with respect to v i is positive for all values of v i . Thus the optimal value of v i is −∞, the optimal pricing plan is (pi1C, pi2C)=(μμi0,∞), and the associated seller's expected profit is μμi0c.

  • When δ>1 and γ i >1/μ, first-order derivative with respect to v i is negative for all values of v i . Thus the optimal value of v i is ∞, the optimal pricing plan is (pi1F, pi2F)=(∞,δ(μμi0)), and the associated seller's expected profit is δ(μμi0)−c.

Let v i CP>0 be the positive solution to equation (A.19) and v i CN=−v i CP be the negative solution. Use the same mathematical deduction as that in the proofs of Propositions 1, 2 and 3, v i CP is a local maximizer when δ<1 while v i CN is a local maximizer when δ>1. Thus, there exists a cutoff type γ lp C such that its corresponding ν lp C satisfy Π i C(v lp C)=μμi0c and that v i CP is the global maximizer for all γ i <γ lp C. The cutoff values, γ lp C and v lp C, satisfy the following equations simultaneously:

It is worth noting that if we replace the term (μμi0) with μ, equation (A.20) is the same as equation (A.5). This means that when the best outside option gives type-i consumer a utility of μi0, the pricing plan is the same as the case of no competition and the consumer's valuation is μμi0. Combining the two equations above, we obtain a relationship between γ lp C and v lp C:

The equation above shows that γ ip Cv ip C is constant regardless the value of μμi0, thus v lp C decreases in μi0 while γ lp C increases in μi0.

Similarly, there exists a cutoff type γ mp C such that the corresponding v mp C satisfy Π i C(v mp C)=δ(μμi0)−c and that γ mp C is the global maximizer for all γ i <γ mp C. The cutoff values, γ mp C and v mp C, satisfy the following equations simultaneously:

With the same reasoning as above, we can conclude that the absolute value of v mp C decreases in μi0 while γ mp C increases in μi0. Combine both cases we can conclude that the price dispersion decreases in μi0 while the cutoff valuations increase in μi0 increases. □

Proof of Proposition 8

Before we solve the optimization problem, let us first compare the consumers’ expected utility for a given pricing plan {p1, p2}. The expected utility for a low-valuation consumer is

where v=p1δ c p2. The expected utility for a high-valuation consumer is

Let μ d =μ1μ2, the above equation can be written as

Owing to the common degree of rationality, the probability of a consumer chooses to purchase in period 1 depends only on the adjusted price difference. A high-valuation consumer behaves the same as the low-valuation consumer does provided that the pricing plan induce both types of consumer to participate. Moreover, the expected utility of a high valuation consumer is higher than that of a low-valuation consumer by a fixed amount (μ d ) for a given pricing plan. With that insight in mind, we can move on to solve the problem. Let v i =ui2ui1=pi1δ c pi2. Since μ1p21=(μ1μ2)+(μ2p21)=μ d +u21 and μ1δ c p22=(μ1μ2)+(μ2δ c p22)=μ d +u22, (IC-1,2) can thus be simplified as

and similarly (IC-2,1) can be written as

It is clear that (PC-2) binds, and thus We can write p21 in terms of μ2 and v2: Similarly, δ c p22 can be written as Suppose (IC-1,2) binds, then , that is, Consequently, p11 equals and δ c p12 equals

It is easy to verify that both (PC-1) and (IC-2,1) are satisfied:

The expected profit function can then be written as

The derivatives with respect to v1 and v2 are as follows:

Let v1p>0 and v1n<0 be the two solutions for (A.25) and v2p>0 and v2n<0 for (A.26). Since (A.25) and (A.26) must be satisfied simultaneously, v1p=v2p=vp and v1n=v2n=vn. For the expected profit function to achieve its maximum, we also need

Thus, the local maximizers are (v1, v2)=(vp, vp) when δ<1 and (v1, v2)=(vn, vn) when δ>1.

Case 1: δ<1

A candidate solution is the corner solution (v1, v2)=(−∞,−∞), with a profit of μ2c. ΠH(vp, vp) is a global maximum if it is greater than μ2c. We need to compare to the case where the seller only serve type-1 consumers. Here only (PC-1) needs to be satisfied; thus, Let Π1 be the seller's expected profit, which can be written as

where v1 satisfies Since Π1(v1) decreases in ρ1, there exists a cutoff value for ρ1 such that Π1(v1)=ΠH(vp, vp),

To summarize, the seller is interested in serving high-valuation consumers when the proportion is large enough (ρ1>ρ1c), and when the proportion of high-valuation consumers is low, the seller sets the price as if it only serves type 2 consumers.

Case 2: δ>1

In this case, we obtain

The corner solution (v1, v2)=(∞,∞) gives rise to the expected payoff ΠH(∞,∞)=δμ2c. Thus, ΠH(vn, vn) is a global maximum if it is greater than δμ2c. □

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Cai, W., Chen, YJ. Intertemporal pricing with boundedly rational consumers. J Revenue Pricing Manag 11, 421–452 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1057/rpm.2011.14

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1057/rpm.2011.14

Keywords

Navigation