Skip to main content
Log in

Health justice after the social determinants of health revolution

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Social Theory & Health Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Social Determinants of Health (SDH) theorists claim that the distribution of social goods such as income, housing and education, has as great or greater an impact on health outcome than does health care, narrowly construed. This article attempts to integrate this claim into a plausible theory of justice. I argue that such a theory must be both political, in that it focuses on goods that states can distribute or regulate effectively and appropriately, and holistic, in that it must integrate the various values that are relevant to distribution into a plausible overall theory. While SDH-based theories are appropriately political, many of their exponents tend to undertake the task of integration in an implausibly monistic manner. I argue that monists about health are caught between the horns of an unattractive dilemma: either they employ a narrow conception of health, in which case their prescriptions are grounded in an implausible conception of the human good, and give rise to an extreme form of paternalism; or they use a broader conception of health, which leads them to address the challenge of holism in a purely rhetorical manner. I argue for a pluralistic mode of integration, one that accepts that social goods are regulated by both consequentialist and non-consequentialist considerations, and that the range of consequences that are relevant do not relate merely to health.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For example, Canadian provinces spend anywhere from 50 to 100 per cent more for health care and related services than they do for education. See the 2009 data collected by the École nationale d’administration publique, at etatscanadiens-canadiangovernments.enap.ca/en/nav.aspx?sortcode=2.0.3.3, accessed 26 April 2015.

  2. The main protagonists in the ‘bedtime story debate’ are Brighouse and Swift (2009), Mason, (2006, 2011) and Segall (2011).

  3. Paradigmatic luck egalitarians would include at least Dworkin (2000) and Cohen (1989).

  4. Why start from the goods that are already distributed or regulated by developed modern states in trying to build up a theory of the kinds of goods that states ought to distribute and regulate? Briefly, two reasons can be adduced. First, normative political theory should in my view contribute to the improvement and reform of already existing institutions. In Rawlsian ‘ realistic utopian’ spirit, it should attempt to show how institutions of tolerably decent states should change in order to realize the values that underpin them. Second, and again in Rawlsian spirit, starting (but not ending) with a list of goods already distributed by states can be seen as part of an exercise in reflective equilibrium. By moving back and forth between conceptions of state action that are implicit in the institutional design and functioning of modern states and abstract norms such as appropriateness and effectiveness, the hope is that we will be able to contruct a theory that is both defensible on normative grounds and capable of informing institutional reform. I thank an anonymous reviewer for this journal for having pressed me on this point.

  5. An example of a piecemeal approach with respect to health can be found in Segall (2013, pp. 93–94), and more generally in Segall (2010).

  6. See my ‘Sites of Deliberation in Contemporary Electoral Systems’, forthcoming in The Journal of Parliamentary and Political Law. The term ‘platform’ is used here deliberately in order to echo the kinds of proposals that emanate from political parties, and that are presented to the democratic voting public for consideration in general elections.

  7. It should be clear that the reference to monism here should be understood politically rather than morally or metaphysically. Monism as employed here is the view that the evaluation of state action should be carried out with reference to one unique value or outcome. It is not a view about what is ultimately of value, although political monists may (but need not) ground their political positions in deeper and more general philosophical positions. I thank an anonymous reviewer for having pressed me on this point.

  8. Monism can be grounded in the thought that ‘health is a better guide to the quality of life than measures of real income and GNPpc’ (Wilkinson, 1996, p. 215). It can also be grounded in the view that people ascribe great, irreducible value to health (Marmot, 2013). For an instance of a monist theory, see Ruger (2009). For a kindred critique of health monism, see Latham (2013).

  9. For such a sufficientarian view in the area of health, see Powers and Faden (2006).

  10. This conception of health has been famously adopted by the World Health Organization, according to which ‘health is a state of complete physical, mental and social well-being and not merely the absence of disease or infirmity’. An instance of this expansionary move in the philosophical literature is Venkatapuram (2013).

  11. Cf. my ‘Integrating Intermediate Goods to Theories of Distributive Justice’, in Res Publica, DOI 10.1007/s11158-015-9274-1, 2015.

  12. See my ‘Sites of Deliberation in Contemporary Electoral Systems’ (ibid.)

References

  • Arneson, R. (1989) Equality and equality of opportunity for welfare. Philosophical Studies 56 (1): 77–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brighouse, H. and Swift, A. (2009) Legitimate parental partiality. Philosophy and Public Affairs 37 (1): 43–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, G.A. (1989) On the currency of egalitarian justice. Ethics 99 (4): 906–944.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daniels, N. (2008) Just Health. Meeting Health Needs Fairly. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daniels, N., Kennedy, B. and Kawachi, I. (2004) Health and inequality, or, why justice is good for our health. In: S. Anand, F. Peter and A. Sen (eds.) Public Health, Ethics, and Equity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 63–92.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (2000) Sovereign Virtue. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodin, R. (1995) Political ideals and political practice. British Journal of Political Science 25 (1): 37–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hohmann, J. (2013) The Right to Housing. Law, Concepts, Possibilities. London: Hart Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latham, S.R. (2013) On some difficulties for any theory of global health justice. In: J. Coggan and S. Gola (eds.) Global Health and International Community. London: Bloomsbury Academic, pp. 17–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marmot, M. (2008) Health in a just society. The Lancet 372 (9642): 881–882.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marmot, M. (2013) Fair society healthy lives. In: N. Eyal, S.A. Hurst, O.F. Norheim and D. Wikler (eds.) Inequalities in Health. Concepts, Measures, and Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mason, A. (2006) Levelling the Playing Field: The Idea of Equality of Opportunity and its Place in Egalitarian Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mason, A. (2011) Putting story-reading to bed: A reply to Segall. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 14 (1): 81–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J.S. ([1861] 2010) Considerations on Representative Government. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Powers, M. and Faden, R. (2006) Social Justice. The Moral Foundations of Public Health and Health Policy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1971) A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1977) The basic structure as subject. American Philosophical Quarterly 14 (2): 159–165.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruger, J.P. (2009) Health and Social Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Segall, S. (2010) Health, Luck, and Justice. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Segall, S. (2011) If you’re a luck egalitarian, how come you read bedtime stories to your children? Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 14 (1): 23–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Segall, S. (2013) Equality and Opportunity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Venkatapuram, S. (2013) Health, vital goals and central human capabilities. Bioethics 27 (5): 271–279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Venkatapuram, S. and Marmot, M. (2009) Epidemiology and social justice in light of social determinants of health research. Bioethics 23 (2): 79–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilkinson, R. (1996) Unhealthy Societies. The Affliction of Inequality. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wilkinson, R. and Marmot, M. (2005) Social Determinants of Health. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkinson, R. and Pickett, K. (2009) The Spirit Level. Why Equality is Better for Everyone. London: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author wishes to thank Adina Preda, Kristin Voigt, Thomas Schramme and Sridhar Venkatapuram, among others, for their helpful comments on that occasion. He also wishes to thank two anonymous referees for this journal for their extensive comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Additional information

An earlier version of this article was delivered at a symposium on health justice at the Zentrum für Interdisciplinarische Forschung at the University of Bielefeld.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Weinstock, D. Health justice after the social determinants of health revolution. Soc Theory Health 13, 437–453 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1057/sth.2015.11

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1057/sth.2015.11

Keywords

Navigation